Beyond Evidence-Based Belief Formation: How Normative Ideas Have Constrained Conceptual Change Research

Main Article Content

Stellan Ohlsson

Abstract

The cognitive sciences, including psychology and education, have their roots in antiquity. In the historically early disciplines like logic and philosophy, the purpose of inquiry was normative. Logic sought to formalize valid inferences, and the various branches of philosophy sought to identify true and certain knowledge. Normative principles are irrelevant for descriptive, empirical sciences like psychology. Normative concepts have nevertheless strongly influenced cognitive research in general and conceptual change research in particular. Studies of conceptual change often ask why students do not abandon their misconceptions when presented with falsifying evidence. But there is little reason to believe that people evolved to conform to normative principles of belief management and conceptual change. When we put the normative traditions aside, we can consider a broader range of hypotheses about conceptual change. As an illustration, the pragmatist focus on action and habits is articulated into a psychological theory that claims that cognitive utility, not the probability of truth, is the key variable that determines belief revision and conceptual change.

Article Details

How to Cite
Ohlsson, S. (2013). Beyond Evidence-Based Belief Formation: How Normative Ideas Have Constrained Conceptual Change Research. Frontline Learning Research, 1(2), 70–85. https://doi.org/10.14786/flr.v1i2.58
Section
Articles
Author Biography

Stellan Ohlsson, University of Illinois at Chicago

Professor of Psychology

Adjunct Professor of Computer Science

References

Allport, G. W. (1958/1979). The nature of prejudice (2nd ed.). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.
Anderson, J. R. (2007). How can the human mind occur in the physical universe (pp. 159-165)? Oxford UP.
Broughton, S. H., Sinatra, G. M., & Nussbaum, E. M. (2013). “Pluto has been a planet my whole life!” Emotions, attitudes, and conceptual change in elementary students’ learning about Pluto’s reclassification. Research in Science Education, 43, 529-550.
Chi, M. T. H. (2005). Commonsense conceptions of emergent processes: Why some misconceptions are robust. The Journal of the Learning Sciences, 14, 161-199.
Chi, M.T.H. (2008). Three types of conceptual change: Belief revision, mental model transformation, and categorical shift. In S.Vosniadou (Ed.), Handbook of research on conceptual change (pp. 61-82). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Claggett, M. (1959). The science of mechanics in the middle ages. Madison, Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press.
Cosejo, D. G., Oesterreich, J., & Ohlsson, S. (2009). Re-categorization: Restructuring in categorization In N.A. Taatgen & H. van Rijn (Eds.), Proceedings of the 31th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.
Evans, J. St. B. T. (2007). Hypothetical thinking: Dual processes in reasoning and judgment. New York: Psychology Press.
Festinger, L. (1957/1962). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Frank, P. (1952). The origin of the separation between science and philosophy. Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, 80(2), 115-139.
Gabbay, D., & Woods, J. (2001). The new logic. Logic Journal of the Interest Group in Pure and Applied Logics, vol. 9, pp. 141-174.
Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.
Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2006). How we reason. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.
Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kuhn, T. S. (1957). The Copernican revolution: Planetary astronomy in the development of Western thought. New York: Random House.
Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Lakatos, I. (1980). Philosophical papers (vol. 1): The methodology of scientific research programmes). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Limón, M. (2001). On the cognitive conflict as an instructional strategy for conceptual change: a critical appraisal. Learning and Instruction, 11, 357-380.
Margolis, H. (1987). Patterns, thinking, and cognition: A theory of judgment. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Margolis, H. (1993). Paradigms and barriers: How habits of mind govern scientific beliefs. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Offit, P. A. (2011). Deadly choices: How the anti-vaccine movement threatens us all. New York: Basic Books.
Ohlsson, S. (2009). Resubsumption: A possible mechanism for conceptual change and belief revision. Educational Psychologist, 44, 20-40.
Ohlsson, S. (2011). Deep learning: How the mind overrides experience. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Oreskes, N. (2004). Beyond the ivory tower: The scientific consensus on climate change. Science, 306, 1686.
Peirce, C. S. (1878). How to make our ideas clear. Popular Science Monthly, vol. 12, pp. 286-302. [Reprinted in N. Houser and C. Kloesel (Eds.), The essential Peirce: Selected philosophical writings (vol. 1, pp. 124-141). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.]
Pettigrew, T. F. (1998). Intergroup contact theory. Annual Review of Psychology, vol. 49, pp. 65-85.
Posner, G. J., Strike, K. A., Hewson, P. W., & Gertzog, W. A. (1982). Accommodation of a scientific conception: Toward a theory of conceptual change. Science Education, 66, 211-27.
Robin, N., & Ohlsson, S. (1989) Impetus then and now: A detailed comparison between Jean Buridan and a single contemporary subject. In D. E. Herget (Ed.), Proceedings of the First International Conference on the History and Philosophy of Science in Science Teaching, Florida State University, Tallahassee, Florida, November 6 – 10 (pp. 292-305). Science Education and Department of Philosophy, Florida State University.
Rokeach, M. (1960). The open and closed mind. New York: Basic Books.
Rokeach, M. (1970). Beliefs, attitudes, and values: A theory of organization and change. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Schiller, F. C. S. (1905). The definition of ‘pragmatism’ and ‘humanism’. Mind, 14, 235-240.
Sinatra, G. M., & Pintrich, P. R., (Eds.), (2003). Intentional conceptual change. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Stitch, S. P. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Strike, K. A., & Posner, G. J. (1992). A revisionist theory of conceptual change. In R. A. Duschl and R. J. Hamilton (Eds.), Philosophy of science, cognitive psychology, and educational theory and practice (pp. 147-176). New York: State University of New York Press.
Vosniadou, S., & Skopeliti, I. (2013). Conceptual change from the framework theory side of the fence. Science & Education, DOI 10.1007/s11191-013-9640-3.
Wason, P. C., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1972). Psychology of reasoning: Structure and content. London, UK: B. T. Batsford.
Watson, J. D., & Crick, F. H C. (1953). A structure for deoxyribose nucleic acid. Nature, vol. 171, pp. 73